Monad laws in presence of bottoms

I just realised that many common monads do not obey the monad laws when it comes to bottoms. E.g. for the Reader monad: undefined >>= return /= undefined return () >>= undefined /= undefined return () >>= const undefined /= undefined return undefined >>= \x -> case x of () -> return () /= undefined Not a long time ago David Barbour argued on this list that bottoms should be ignored when checking the monad laws. Is that the commonly accepted interpretation of the laws? Is there any other interpretation in which the Reader monad obeys the laws? -- Roman I. Cheplyaka :: http://ro-che.info/

On Mon, Feb 20, 2012 at 7:42 PM, Roman Cheplyaka
Is there any other interpretation in which the Reader monad obeys the laws?
If "selective strictness" (the seq combinator) would exclude function types, the difference between undefined and \_ -> undefined could not be observed. This reminds me of the different language levels used by the free theorem generator [1] and the discussions whether seq should have a type-class constraint.. Sebastian [1]: http://www-ps.iai.uni-bonn.de/cgi-bin/free-theorems-webui.cgi

* Sebastian Fischer
On Mon, Feb 20, 2012 at 7:42 PM, Roman Cheplyaka
wrote: Is there any other interpretation in which the Reader monad obeys the laws?
If "selective strictness" (the seq combinator) would exclude function types, the difference between undefined and \_ -> undefined could not be observed. This reminds me of the different language levels used by the free theorem generator [1] and the discussions whether seq should have a type-class constraint..
It's not just about functions. The same holds for the lazy Writer monad, for instance. -- Roman I. Cheplyaka :: http://ro-che.info/

On 2/21/12 2:17 AM, Roman Cheplyaka wrote:
* Sebastian Fischer
[2012-02-21 00:28:13+0100] On Mon, Feb 20, 2012 at 7:42 PM, Roman Cheplyaka
wrote: Is there any other interpretation in which the Reader monad obeys the laws?
If "selective strictness" (the seq combinator) would exclude function types, the difference between undefined and \_ -> undefined could not be observed. This reminds me of the different language levels used by the free theorem generator [1] and the discussions whether seq should have a type-class constraint..
It's not just about functions. The same holds for the lazy Writer monad, for instance.
That's a similar sort of issue, just about whether undefined == (undefined,undefined) or not. If the equality holds then tuples would be domain products[1], but domain products do not form domains! In order to get a product which does form a domain, we'd need to use the smash product[2] instead. Unfortunately we can't have our cake and eat it too (unless we get rid of bottom entirely). Both this issue and the undefined == (\_ -> undefined) issue come down to whether we're allowed to eta expand functions or tuples/records. While this is a well-studies topic, I don't know that anyone's come up with a really pretty answer to the dilemma. [1] Also a category-theoretic product. [2] Aka: data SmashProduct a b = SmashProduct !a !b -- Live well, ~wren

Ehm... why exactly don't domain products form domains? On 21 Feb 2012, at 19:44, wren ng thornton wrote:
On 2/21/12 2:17 AM, Roman Cheplyaka wrote:
* Sebastian Fischer
[2012-02-21 00:28:13+0100] On Mon, Feb 20, 2012 at 7:42 PM, Roman Cheplyaka
wrote: Is there any other interpretation in which the Reader monad obeys the laws?
If "selective strictness" (the seq combinator) would exclude function types, the difference between undefined and \_ -> undefined could not be observed. This reminds me of the different language levels used by the free theorem generator [1] and the discussions whether seq should have a type-class constraint..
It's not just about functions. The same holds for the lazy Writer monad, for instance.
That's a similar sort of issue, just about whether undefined == (undefined,undefined) or not. If the equality holds then tuples would be domain products[1], but domain products do not form domains! In order to get a product which does form a domain, we'd need to use the smash product[2] instead. Unfortunately we can't have our cake and eat it too (unless we get rid of bottom entirely).
Both this issue and the undefined == (\_ -> undefined) issue come down to whether we're allowed to eta expand functions or tuples/records. While this is a well-studies topic, I don't know that anyone's come up with a really pretty answer to the dilemma.
[1] Also a category-theoretic product.
[2] Aka: data SmashProduct a b = SmashProduct !a !b
-- Live well, ~wren
_______________________________________________ Haskell-Cafe mailing list Haskell-Cafe@haskell.org http://www.haskell.org/mailman/listinfo/haskell-cafe

On 2/21/12 11:27 AM, MigMit wrote:
Ehm... why exactly don't domain products form domains?
One important property of domains[1] is that they have a unique bottom element. Given domains A and B, let us denote the domain product as: (A,B) def= { (a,b) | a <- A, b <- B } Which will inherit an ordering in the obvious/free way from the domain orderings on A and B. Since both A and B are domains, they have bottom elements: exists a0:A. forall a:A. (a0 <=_A a) exists b0:B. forall b:B. (b0 <=_B b) However, there is no free ordering on: { (a0,b) | b <- B } \cup { (a,b0) | a <- A } So all of those are minimal elements of (A,B) but none of them is a unique minimum; hence (A,B) is not a domain. The smash product gets around this because it takes all those elements and makes them equal, just like a strict tuple would in Haskell. [1] This is in the sense of domain theory. It has nothing (per se) to do with the many other uses of the term "domain" in mathematics. -- Live well, ~wren

22.02.2012, 09:30, "wren ng thornton"
On 2/21/12 11:27 AM, MigMit wrote:
Ehm... why exactly don't domain products form domains?
One important property of domains[1] is that they have a unique bottom element. Given domains A and B, let us denote the domain product as:
(A,B) def= { (a,b) | a <- A, b <- B }
Which will inherit an ordering in the obvious/free way from the domain orderings on A and B. Since both A and B are domains, they have bottom elements:
exists a0:A. forall a:A. (a0 <=_A a) exists b0:B. forall b:B. (b0 <=_B b)
However, there is no free ordering on:
{ (a0,b) | b <- B } \cup { (a,b0) | a <- A }
What? By definition, since, a0 <= a and b0 <= b, we have (a0, b0) <= (a0, b) and (a0, b0) <= (a0, b0), so, (a0, b0) is clearly the bottom of A\times B.
So all of those are minimal elements of (A,B) but none of them is a unique minimum; hence (A,B) is not a domain.
The smash product gets around this because it takes all those elements and makes them equal, just like a strict tuple would in Haskell.
[1] This is in the sense of domain theory. It has nothing (per se) to do with the many other uses of the term "domain" in mathematics.
Sorry, isn't the domain theory a part of mathematics?

On 2/22/12 1:45 AM, Miguel Mitrofanov wrote:
However, there is no free ordering on:
{ (a0,b) | b<- B } \cup { (a,b0) | a<- A }
What? By definition, since, a0<= a and b0<= b, we have (a0, b0)<= (a0, b) and (a0, b0)<= (a0, b0), so, (a0, b0) is clearly the bottom of A\times B.
Sorry, the ordering relation on domain products is defined by: (a1,b1) <=_(A,B) (a2,b2) if and only if a1 <=_A a2 and b1 <=_B b2
[1] This is in the sense of domain theory. It has nothing (per se) to do with the many other uses of the term "domain" in mathematics.
Sorry, isn't the domain theory a part of mathematics?
Sure, domain theory is a part of mathematics, but the term "domain" is used to mean a bunch of different and largely unrelated things. For example: * in type theory and set theory the "domain" of a function is the set of inputs on which it's defined * in domain theory a "domain" is a partial order with a least element and the property that every non-empty countable chain has a least upper bound * in ring theory a "domain" is is a ring which has no left nor right zero-divisors * in analysis a "domain" is any connected open subset of a finite-dimensional vector space etc. -- Live well, ~wren

22.02.2012, 11:20, "wren ng thornton"
On 2/22/12 1:45 AM, Miguel Mitrofanov wrote:
However, there is no free ordering on:
{ (a0,b) | b<- B } \cup { (a,b0) | a<- A } What? By definition, since, a0<= a and b0<= b, we have (a0, b0)<= (a0, b) and (a0, b0)<= (a0, b0), so, (a0, b0) is clearly the bottom of A\times B.
Sorry, the ordering relation on domain products is defined by:
(a1,b1) <=_(A,B) (a2,b2) if and only if a1 <=_A a2 and b1 <=_B b2
So, you're agreeing with me? a0 <=_A a, b0 <=_B b0, so (a0, b0) <=_(A,B) (a, b0). Right?

On 2/22/12 2:20 AM, wren ng thornton wrote:
On 2/22/12 1:45 AM, Miguel Mitrofanov wrote:
However, there is no free ordering on:
{ (a0,b) | b <- B } \cup { (a,b0) | a <- A }
What? By definition, since, a0 <= a and b0 <= b, we have (a0, b0) <= (a0,b) and (a0, b0) <= (a0, b0), so, (a0, b0) is clearly the bottom of A\times B.
Sorry, the ordering relation on domain products is defined by:
(a1,b1) <=_(A,B) (a2,b2) if and only if a1 <=_A a2 and b1 <=_B b2
Sorry, I misread what you wrote. Yes, of course you're correct. I can't recall off-hand why it is that domain products break things; I'll have to look it up. -- Live well, ~wren

On Tue, Feb 21, 2012 at 10:44 AM, wren ng thornton
That's a similar sort of issue, just about whether undefined == (undefined,undefined) or not. If the equality holds then tuples would be domain products[1], but domain products do not form domains! ... [1] Also a category-theoretic product.
This doesn't make much sense to me, either. If it's a category theoretic product in a category of domains, then the product must be a domain, no?
In order to get a product which does form a domain, we'd need to use the smash product[2] instead. Unfortunately we can't have our cake and eat it too (unless we get rid of bottom entirely).
You don't have to get rid of bottom entirely (I think). If you make matches against products irrefutable, then you're again in the situation of seq being the only thing able to distinguish between _|_ and (_|_, _|_), so we could keep the current implementation (which is efficient) without it being possible to observe within the language. You just have to make seq not be magic on products. Miranda did this, except it still had a seq which exposed the lie. The problem with this is that you can easily build up a product that is a bunch of thunks and cause a stack overflow; I _think_ that's more of a concern than doing the same with a function. So in practice it might be harder to do without seq on tuples. -- Dan

On 2/21/12 11:54 AM, Dan Doel wrote:
On Tue, Feb 21, 2012 at 10:44 AM, wren ng thornton
wrote: That's a similar sort of issue, just about whether undefined == (undefined,undefined) or not. If the equality holds then tuples would be domain products[1], but domain products do not form domains! ... [1] Also a category-theoretic product.
This doesn't make much sense to me, either. If it's a category theoretic product in a category of domains, then the product must be a domain, no?
It's a category-theoretic product, but not for the category of domains. Let Set be the category of sets and set-theoretic functions. And let pDCPO be the category of (pointed) domains and their homomorphisms. The category-theoretic product of A and B is just some triple (C, pi_A : C -> A, pi_B : C -> B) such that forall D, forall f : D -> A, and forall g : D -> B, there exists a unique h : D -> C such that f = pi_A . h and g = pi_B . h ---in other words, it's the limit of a functor from the category with two objects and no morphisms which maps one object to A and the other object to B. The (domain-theoretic) domain product was discussed in my previous message to MigMit. It's a category-theoretic product in Set (among other categories) because the necessary morphisms exist and they satisfy the necessary equations. Moreover, in Set the domain product coincides with the cartesian product (we just forget about the orderings on the input domains and the resulting product). Hence, since the cartesian product is a category-theoretic product for Set, we know that the domain product must be a category-theoretic product in Set. However, the domain product is not a category-theoretic product in pDCPO. First off, the objects in pDCPO are domains, but since the domain product of A and B has no bottom it can't be a domain, so it can't be an object in pDCPO. Moreover, the morphisms in pDCPO will preserve the domain structure--- but there's no way to do that for a map from some domain C to the domain product of A and B, because there's no way to map the bottom of C to the bottom of the domain product (because there isn't one!). Conversely, the smash product is a category-theoretic product in pDCPO, but not in Set. Since every domain homomorphism must map bottoms to bottoms, it follows that f(d0) = a0 and g(d0) = b0. From this we have the necessary continuity to ensure that C, pi_A, and pi_B all exist in pDCPO. However, since there exist set-theoretic functions f and g which do not have that special property, the smash product is going to lose information about the non-bottom component of the product and so it cannot satisfy the necessary category-theoretic equations (in Set). For more on the category-theoretic study of domain theory, see http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/~axj/pub/papers/handy1.pdf. You can search the pdf for "pointed dcpo" to jump to the relevant sections. Of course there are many different category-theoretic formalizations of domain theory, pDCPO is just one of them. To get a survey of the terrain, you may want to take a look at http://seclab.web.cs.illinois.edu/wp-content/uploads/2011/04/Gunter85.pdf. For a more direct introduction to domain theory and its application to lazy languages, see Geoffrey Burn's _Lazy Functional Languages: Abstract Interpretation and Compilation_. -- Live well, ~wren

On Wed, Feb 22, 2012 at 1:40 AM, wren ng thornton
It's a category-theoretic product, but not for the category of domains. Let Set be the category of sets and set-theoretic functions. And let pDCPO be the category of (pointed) domains and their homomorphisms.
The (domain-theoretic) domain product was discussed in my previous message to MigMit. It's a category-theoretic product in Set (among other categories) because the necessary morphisms exist and they satisfy the necessary equations. Moreover, in Set the domain product coincides with the cartesian product (we just forget about the orderings on the input domains and the resulting product). Hence, since the cartesian product is a category-theoretic product for Set, we know that the domain product must be a category-theoretic product in Set.
Well, like Miguel, I don't see the problem with choosing the ordering: (a,b) <= (a', b') iff a <= a' and b <= b' This makes (a0, b0) the bottom element. The only difference with Haskell's tuple types is that it lacks an extra element below (a0, b0); it's unlifted. It also seems to me that this _is_ the correct product for domains, unless I'm still sketchy on what you mean by domain. I don't think it matters that we're only considering strict homomorphisms.
Conversely, the smash product is a category-theoretic product in pDCPO, but not in Set. Since every domain homomorphism must map bottoms to bottoms, it follows that f(d0) = a0 and g(d0) = b0. From this we have the necessary continuity to ensure that C, pi_A, and pi_B all exist in pDCPO. However, since there exist set-theoretic functions f and g which do not have that special property, the smash product is going to lose information about the non-bottom component of the product and so it cannot satisfy the necessary category-theoretic equations (in Set).
The smash product is not a product for domains (in general), either.
You are not allowed to throw away the components for such a product,
because given a homomorphism f that maps everything to a0, pi_B .

On 2/22/12 2:37 AM, Dan Doel wrote:
unless I'm still sketchy on what you mean by domain. I don't think it matters that we're only considering strict homomorphisms.
I think part of the problem is that there are many different ideas of what exact properties a domain has. The one I'm most familiar with are consistently-complete \omega-algebraic cpos, but they're far from the only option. Also, I may be misremembering my facts about how the domain theory and the category theory fit together. I do recall that domain products break some sorts of desirable properties, but that may be due to something else about them. -- Live well, ~wren

On 2/21/12 11:54 AM, Dan Doel wrote:
You don't have to get rid of bottom entirely (I think). If you make matches against products irrefutable, then you're again in the situation of seq being the only thing able to distinguish between _|_ and (_|_, _|_), so we could keep the current implementation (which is efficient) without it being possible to observe within the language. You just have to make seq not be magic on products. Miranda did this, except it still had a seq which exposed the lie.
I thought Miranda identified _|_ with (_|_,_|_) ...though I admit I never really played around with Miranda. In any case, the point is that the weirdness of Haskell's products and function spaces are related around this issue of eta expansion. Haskell's sums are also weird (they're not category-theoretic coproducts), but that's not clearly an issue with eta. When it comes to practical utility, I think the choices Haskell made are quite nice. I'd love for smash products to have built-in syntax like tuples do, so I could use them cleanly rather than doing (((,) $! a) $! b) or defining my own ADT for them; but I understand entirely about why the Haskell committee decided that having two different versions of products/tuples would lead to API bloat and user confusion. However, while Haskell's choices are quite nice from a practical perspective, when it comes to theoretical rigor they're quite ugly. And that's the issue we're running into here when trying to figure out a theoretically sound way of defining how monads should behave with respect to bottoms. -- Live well, ~wren

On 2/21/12 10:44 AM, wren ng thornton wrote:
but domain products do not form domains! In order to get a product which does form a domain, we'd need to use the smash product[2] instead. Unfortunately we can't have our cake and eat it too
Bah, I don't know why my wires were crossed yesterday. It's *coproducts* where the category-theoretic and domain-theoretic definitions are at odds. For *products*, the issues are just about whether the category is cartesian closed and the like (i.e., divergence between products and tensors). Up too late with too little coffee, no doubt. My apologies for causing confusion. -- Live well, ~wren
participants (6)
-
Dan Doel
-
MigMit
-
Miguel Mitrofanov
-
Roman Cheplyaka
-
Sebastian Fischer
-
wren ng thornton